Modification de The communitarian perspective

Attention : vous n’êtes pas connecté(e). Votre adresse IP sera visible de tout le monde si vous faites des modifications. Si vous vous connectez ou créez un compte, vos modifications seront attribuées à votre propre nom d’utilisateur(rice) et vous aurez d’autres avantages.

La modification peut être annulée. Veuillez vérifier les différences ci-dessous pour voir si c’est bien ce que vous voulez faire, puis publier ces changements pour finaliser l’annulation de cette modification.

Version actuelle Votre texte
Ligne 1 : Ligne 1 :
{{Infobox Lecture
| image =
| image_caption =
| cours = [[Political Theory]]
| faculté =
| département =
| professeurs = [[Matteo Gianni]]<ref>[https://unige.ch/sciences-societe/speri/membres/matteo-gianni/ Page personnelle de Matteo Gianni sur le site de l'Université de Genève]</ref><ref>Concordia University, Faculty of Arts and Science - Department of Political Science. “Dr. Matteo Gianni.” Dr. Matteo Gianni, https://www.concordia.ca/artsci/polisci/wssr/all-guest-lecturers/matteogianni.html</ref><ref>Profil de Matteo Gianni sur ResearchGate: https://www.researchgate.net/scientific-contributions/2010087511_Matteo_Gianni</ref><ref>Profil Linkedin de Matteo Gianni - https://www.linkedin.com/in/matteo-gianni-2438b135/?originalSubdomain=ch</ref><ref>[https://scholar.google.com/citations?user=QP7aLBAAAAAJ&hl=fr Matteo Gianni - Citations Google Scholar]</ref><ref>“Matteo Gianni - Auteur - Ressources De La Bibliothèque Nationale De France.” Data.bnf.fr, https://data.bnf.fr/fr/16166342/matteo_gianni/.</ref><ref>“Matteo Gianni: Università Degli Studi Di Udine / University of Udine.” Academia.edu, https://uniud.academia.edu/MatteoGianni.</ref>
| enregistrement =
| lectures =
*[[What is political theory? Epistemological implications]]
*[[What is political theory? Meta-ethical issues]]
*[[The egalitarian theory of distributive justice by John Rawls]]
*[[The theory of rights by Robert Nozick]]
*[[The theory of resources equality by Ronald Dworkin]]
*[[The theory of capabilities of Amartya Sen and Marta Nussbaum]]
*[[The communitarian perspective]]
*[[The multiculturalist perspective]]
}}
We talked about the issue of the difference between a "universalist" and a rather "contextualist" position. On the one hand, we have ideal theories and theories that take more account of the specificities of cases. We have mentioned Rawls as one of the proponents of the ideal theory even though this is not completely true. When [[The egalitarian theory of distributive justice by John Rawls|Rawls]] talks about the reflective equilibrium, he speaks of the general methodological moment of his philosophical position.<ref>Daniels, Norman, "[https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/reflective-equilibrium/ Reflective Equilibrium]", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)</ref> There are two methodological moments which are the thoughtful equilibrium that is a little bit the posture of moral epistemology that he adopts and the original position that are the methodological tools that he uses to make sense with his theory of justice. In its moral epistemology, this reflective equilibrium occupies a fundamental place. It is a back and forth between the general abstract principles and the concrete situations confronting the individual. For Rawls, the determination of the right principle of good theory can be done at a time when this back and forth between intuition and general theory allows us to stop and find a position that can be constructed and defended analytically. This amounts to saying that Rawls is not blind to context if by context we mean the intuitions of individuals. These individuals have intuitions in particular contexts or situations, even if they may be fictitious.  
We talked about the issue of the difference between a "universalist" and a rather "contextualist" position. On the one hand, we have ideal theories and theories that take more account of the specificities of cases. We have mentioned Rawls as one of the proponents of the ideal theory even though this is not completely true. When [[The egalitarian theory of distributive justice by John Rawls|Rawls]] talks about the reflective equilibrium, he speaks of the general methodological moment of his philosophical position.<ref>Daniels, Norman, "[https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/reflective-equilibrium/ Reflective Equilibrium]", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)</ref> There are two methodological moments which are the thoughtful equilibrium that is a little bit the posture of moral epistemology that he adopts and the original position that are the methodological tools that he uses to make sense with his theory of justice. In its moral epistemology, this reflective equilibrium occupies a fundamental place. It is a back and forth between the general abstract principles and the concrete situations confronting the individual. For Rawls, the determination of the right principle of good theory can be done at a time when this back and forth between intuition and general theory allows us to stop and find a position that can be constructed and defended analytically. This amounts to saying that Rawls is not blind to context if by context we mean the intuitions of individuals. These individuals have intuitions in particular contexts or situations, even if they may be fictitious.  


Ligne 131 : Ligne 112 :
== Michael Walzer: Complex Equality (Spheres of Justice: Defending Pluralism and Equality, [1983]1997) ==
== Michael Walzer: Complex Equality (Spheres of Justice: Defending Pluralism and Equality, [1983]1997) ==


[[Fichier:MichaelWalzer-USNA-Lecture.jpg|thumb|200px|Michael Walzer.<ref>“Michael Walzer.” Institute for Advanced Study, https://www.ias.edu/scholars/walzer.</ref><ref>[https://www.sss.ias.edu/sites/sss.ias.edu/files/pdfs/Walzer/Walzer%20CV%2C%20Apr%202019.pdf Michael Walzer's CV on the website of the Institute for Advanced Study] (as of April 2019)</ref>]]
[[Fichier:MichaelWalzer-USNA-Lecture.jpg|thumb|200px|Michael Walzer.<ref>“Michael Walzer.” Institute for Advanced Study, https://www.ias.edu/scholars/walzer.</ref><ref>[https://www.sss.ias.edu/sites/sss.ias.edu/files/pdfs/Walzer/Walzer%20CV%2C%20Apr%202019.pdf Michael Walzer's CV on the website of the Institute for Advanced Study] (update: April 2019)</ref>]]


[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Michael_Walzer Walzer]'s interest is to propose what might be a communitarian theory of distributive justice. He may be less interested in questions of atomism or self ontology. Walzer, in 1983 published ''[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Spheres_of_Justice Spheres of Justice. A defence of pluralism and equality]'' that also attacks Rawls' theory of justice from a particular metaethical standpoint.<ref>Walzer, Michael. Spheres of justice : a defense of pluralism and equality. New York: Basic Books, 1983. Print.</ref><ref>Cohen, Joshua. "[https://dspace.mit.edu/bitstream/handle/1721.1/5448/J-Philosophy-1986.pdf?sequence=1 Review of" Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality]" by Michael Walzer." (1986).</ref><ref>William A. Galston, "Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. Michael Walzer ," Ethics 94, no. 2 (Jan., 1984): 329-333.  https://doi.org/10.1086/292540</ref><ref>Cohen, J., & Walzer, M. (1986). Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. The Journal of Philosophy, 83(8), 457. https://doi.org/10.2307/2026330</ref><ref>Kahn, R. (1984). Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. By Michael Walzer. (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1983. Pp. xviii + 345. $19.95.). American Political Science Review, 78(1), 289–290. https://doi.org/10.2307/1961356</ref> What Walzer proposes is a vision that he describes as interpretive or hermeneutical. For Walzer, the goods that a theory of justice aims to distribute are goods that are already the product of the social meanings that flow from that community. For Walzer, the idea of distributing goods that would be defined as having a general characteristic, universal and therefore valid in any cultural context, does not make it possible to grasp the specific interpretations and meanings that these different goods have in a particular society.  
[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Michael_Walzer Walzer]'s interest is to propose what might be a communitarian theory of distributive justice. He may be less interested in questions of atomism or self ontology. Walzer, in 1983 published ''[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Spheres_of_Justice Spheres of Justice. A defence of pluralism and equality]'' that also attacks Rawls' theory of justice from a particular metaethical standpoint.<ref>Walzer, Michael. Spheres of justice : a defense of pluralism and equality. New York: Basic Books, 1983. Print.</ref><ref>Cohen, Joshua. "[https://dspace.mit.edu/bitstream/handle/1721.1/5448/J-Philosophy-1986.pdf?sequence=1 Review of" Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality]" by Michael Walzer." (1986).</ref><ref>William A. Galston, "Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. Michael Walzer ," Ethics 94, no. 2 (Jan., 1984): 329-333.  https://doi.org/10.1086/292540</ref><ref>Cohen, J., & Walzer, M. (1986). Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. The Journal of Philosophy, 83(8), 457. https://doi.org/10.2307/2026330</ref><ref>Kahn, R. (1984). Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. By Michael Walzer. (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1983. Pp. xviii + 345. $19.95.). American Political Science Review, 78(1), 289–290. https://doi.org/10.2307/1961356</ref> What Walzer proposes is a vision that he describes as interpretive or hermeneutical. For Walzer, the goods that a theory of justice aims to distribute are goods that are already the product of the social meanings that flow from that community. For Walzer, the idea of distributing goods that would be defined as having a general characteristic, universal and therefore valid in any cultural context, does not make it possible to grasp the specific interpretations and meanings that these different goods have in a particular society.  
Ligne 155 : Ligne 136 :
For Walzer, what is important for justice is to avoid that there is a good that dominates over all. If we start from the idea that education is justified on the basis of a certain ideal of what society is, if we start from the idea that divine grace is justified in relation to a certain relationship with the sacred, if we start from the idea that health is justified because a certain relationship with health is necessary for a society to represent itself and for its individuals to live well, if each of these goods must be distributed in a coherent way with it. The tyranny of a good, money or policy on the different spheres violates and distorts the meaning of this distribution and the good as such. For him, this is the problem and the danger he sees with a single distribution criterion. A single distribution to the Rawls would be a simple form of equality, there is a distribution criterion, we distribute it to everyone and we have a form of equality. For Walzer, this is a simple equality; for Rawls, it is a simple equality, that is, a criterion equals a distribution.
For Walzer, what is important for justice is to avoid that there is a good that dominates over all. If we start from the idea that education is justified on the basis of a certain ideal of what society is, if we start from the idea that divine grace is justified in relation to a certain relationship with the sacred, if we start from the idea that health is justified because a certain relationship with health is necessary for a society to represent itself and for its individuals to live well, if each of these goods must be distributed in a coherent way with it. The tyranny of a good, money or policy on the different spheres violates and distorts the meaning of this distribution and the good as such. For him, this is the problem and the danger he sees with a single distribution criterion. A single distribution to the Rawls would be a simple form of equality, there is a distribution criterion, we distribute it to everyone and we have a form of equality. For Walzer, this is a simple equality; for Rawls, it is a simple equality, that is, a criterion equals a distribution.


What he is proposing is a complex equality that is an equality where we are equal in our navigation between different spheres.<ref>Walzer, Michael. "[https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/e/9781315257563/chapters/10.4324/9781315257563-9 Complex equality]." Distributive Justice. Routledge, 2017. 267-294.</ref><ref>Orend, B. (2001). Walzer’s General Theory of Justice. Social Theory and Practice, 27(2), 207–229. https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract200127210</ref><ref>Emily R. Gill, "Walzer's Complex Equality: Constraints & the Right to Be Wrong," Polity 20, no. 1 (Autumn 1987): 32-56.  https://doi.org/10.2307/3234936</ref><ref>Armstrong, C. (2002). Complex equality: Beyond equality and difference. Feminist Theory, 3(1), 67–82. https://doi.org/10.1177/1460012002003001066</ref><ref>Mullenix, Linda S. “The Limits of ‘Complex Equality.’” Harvard Law Review, vol. 97, no. 7, 1984, pp. 1801–1811. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/1340984.</ref><ref>Hooghe, Marc. "[https://limo.libis.be/primo-explore/fulldisplay?docid=LIRIAS1860401&context=L&vid=Lirias&search_scope=Lirias&tab=default_tab&lang=en_US&fromSitemap=1 The Notion of Complex Equality and the Beauty of Alcibiades]." Ethical Perspectives 6.3 (1999): 211-14.</ref> We may be treated differently in the sphere of education, in the sphere of divine grace or in the political sphere, but this is not serious, because it is a complex equality, an equality that is equal to the meaning. On the other hand, if we are in a society where systematically, whatever the sphere, we are always preterite, then in this case there is a problem. Equality for Walzer is not that everyone is treated in the same way, it is that everyone, in accordance with the criteria of redistribution, agrees to be considered just because it is consistent with the meaning that seems right to us. For Walzer, complex equality does not mean that everyone is treated in the same way and that, despite the possibility of distribution in relation to certain goods which may be different, if distribution is justified by the moral reconstruction of the good as such in a particular community, these inequalities are justifiable from the point of view of complex equality, namely to have the right to distribution as it is provided for in the different spheres and not to have the right to someone else.
What he is proposing is a complex equality that is an equality where we are equal in our navigation between different spheres. We may be treated differently in the sphere of education, in the sphere of divine grace or in the political sphere, but this is not serious, because it is a complex equality, an equality that is equal to the meaning. On the other hand, if we are in a society where systematically, whatever the sphere, we are always preterite, then in this case there is a problem. Equality for Walzer is not that everyone is treated in the same way, it is that everyone, in accordance with the criteria of redistribution, agrees to be considered just because it is consistent with the meaning that seems right to us. For Walzer, complex equality does not mean that everyone is treated in the same way and that, despite the possibility of distribution in relation to certain goods which may be different, if distribution is justified by the moral reconstruction of the good as such in a particular community, these inequalities are justifiable from the point of view of complex equality, namely to have the right to distribution as it is provided for in the different spheres and not to have the right to someone else.


Walzer points out that what is important is that the relative nature of distribution does not mean that any form of distribution is acceptable. A social good must be distributed in a way that is independent of its meaning, and in addition, a particular good must not dominate the different distribution criteria. If the "money" good were to be predominant in the various spheres, we would come up with things that were difficult to accept. For Walzer, there is no reason why a community should think in these terms, or at least not find such a community. On the other hand, it finds communities that define their assets differently, which means that one cannot compare the distribution criteria of society A, B, C and D without taking into account its symbolic specificities. Complex equality is a tool, which paradoxically allows him to think of non-domination.<ref>Stassen, Glen. "[https://books.google.fr/books?hl=en&lr=&id=CSnqfpp8VkoC&oi=fnd&pg=PA134&dq=walzer+complex+equality+domination&ots=V1TyDroxBz&sig=0-h8an09RpBVGTOjjLR1N0Hu4JQ#v=onepage&q=walzer%20complex%20equality%20domination&f=false Michael Walzer's situated justice]." The journal of religious ethics (1994): 375-399.</ref> Walzer says that somehow, his conception of equality, in the name of a simple equality that could be the conformity with a rawlsian principle for example, makes it impossible for individuals to be endowed with a distribution of something, but in reality does not think with the meaning that distribution could mean in this context.
Walzer points out that what is important is that the relative nature of distribution does not mean that any form of distribution is acceptable. A social good must be distributed in a way that is independent of its meaning, and in addition, a particular good must not dominate the different distribution criteria. If the "money" good were to be predominant in the various spheres, we would come up with things that were difficult to accept. For Walzer, there is no reason why a community should think in these terms, or at least not find such a community. On the other hand, it finds communities that define their assets differently, which means that one cannot compare the distribution criteria of society A, B, C and D without taking into account its symbolic specificities. Complex equality is a tool, which paradoxically allows him to think of non-domination. Walzer says that somehow, his conception of equality, in the name of a simple equality that could be the conformity with a rawlsian principle for example, makes it impossible for individuals to be endowed with a distribution of something, but in reality does not think with the meaning that distribution could mean in this context.


It is a criticism that comes a little bit closer to [[The theory of capabilities of Amartya Sen and Marta Nussbaum|Sen]]'s criticism that giving everyone who has different needs misses the mark. Here, it would be to give the same thing or treat in the same way different societies or individuals and in addition to different goods that add to the possibility of dominating one good over another. The idea is to give the broad outlines that revolve around this concept which is shared by the great communitarian authors who are the ones of shared meaning. These shared meanings come from a tradition, a culture, a context. For them, nothing is possible without special attention to that. It is possible to imagine that for these authors, Rawls' original position, the veil of ignorance is not just counterintuitive, but misses a fundamental target: it impute the individuals from whom they are.  
It is a criticism that comes a little bit closer to Sen's criticism that giving everyone who has different needs misses the mark. Here, it would be to give the same thing or treat in the same way different societies or individuals and in addition to different goods that add to the possibility of dominating one good over another. The idea is to give the broad outlines that revolve around this concept which is shared by the great communitarian authors who are the ones of shared meaning. These shared meanings come from a tradition, a culture, a context. For them, nothing is possible without special attention to that. It is possible to imagine that for these authors, Rawls' original position, the veil of ignorance is not just counterintuitive, but misses a fundamental target: it impute the individuals from whom they are.  


For them, Rawls' theory can be fascinating as a philosophical exercise, but it is not based on anything because it is wrongly debated and ill-adjusted, in this sense, not only who the individuals are, in terms of anthropological depth, but also their needs and the way in which a certain number of goods reason or not with respect to their life which is their life in a given community and not their life as it could be. There are other representations which, according to them, can only be perceived by resorting to an end work of reconstructing the shared meanings by admitting that these meanings are not the same everywhere. Of course, democratic countries share a certain number of meanings, it is possible to say that they share a certain number of understandings, but if we do not make sense of shared values, we cannot understand why, with more or less similar constitutions and values, there is a system that can provide for direct democracy, others not, some of which allow the death penalty and others not, among other things. For Walzer, if there were no reference to shared values, one would not understand these variations, one would even have to consider it even worse as a species of parasites in the task of translating true democracy or morality into a particular context. For him, these are not parasites, but characteristics that are justified in terms of the meaning individuals give to these goods.
For them, Rawls' theory can be fascinating as a philosophical exercise, but it is not based on anything because it is wrongly debated and ill-adjusted, in this sense, not only who the individuals are, in terms of anthropological depth, but also their needs and the way in which a certain number of goods reason or not with respect to their life which is their life in a given community and not their life as it could be. There are other representations which, according to them, can only be perceived by resorting to an end work of reconstructing the shared meanings by admitting that these meanings are not the same everywhere. Of course, democratic countries share a certain number of meanings, it is possible to say that they share a certain number of understandings, but if we do not make sense of shared values, we cannot understand why, with more or less similar constitutions and values, there is a system that can provide for direct democracy, others not, some of which allow the death penalty and others not, among other things. For Walzer, if there were no reference to shared values, one would not understand these variations, one would even have to consider it even worse as a species of parasites in the task of translating true democracy or morality into a particular context. For him, these are not parasites, but characteristics that are justified in terms of the meaning individuals give to these goods.


Walzer also has a strong democratic critique.<ref>Galston, W. A. (1989). Community, Democracy, Philosophy. Political Theory, 17(1), 119–130. https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591789017001009</ref> He has written texts in which he asserts, for example, the priority of democracy over politics and philosophy.<ref>Walzer, Michael. "[https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/009059178100900307 Philosophy and democracy]." Political theory 9.3 (1981): 379-399.</ref><ref>Walzer, M. (2008). On Promoting Democracy. Ethics & International Affairs, 22(4), 351–355. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-7093.2008.00170.x</ref><ref>Apperley, A. (2001). Philosophy, Democracy and Tyranny: Michael Walzer and Political Philosophy. The European Legacy, 6(1), 7–23. https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770124180</ref> For him, these kinds of models in which philosophers assume the right to explain what democracy is, how it should work is an aporia. According to Walzer, it is democratically that we must succeed in deciding the shared values that characterize us. This is not to say that these shared values do not contain universal forms, because there is a whole dose of universality in a whole number of particular cultures, but it is not for philosophers to decide what we want to do. It is up to us to decide what we want and then we have to justify it so that it becomes acceptable even in other cultural forms.  
Walzer also has a strong democratic critique. He has written texts in which he asserts, for example, the priority of democracy over politics and philosophy. For him, these kinds of models in which philosophers assume the right to explain what democracy is, how it should work is an aporia. According to Walzer, it is democratically that we must succeed in deciding the shared values that characterize us. This is not to say that these shared values do not contain universal forms, because there is a whole dose of universality in a whole number of particular cultures, but it is not for philosophers to decide what we want to do. It is up to us to decide what we want and then we have to justify it so that it becomes acceptable even in other cultural forms.  


Despite these reservations and elements, it is clear that there are still a number of problems in this kind of approach that can be imagined as excessively conservative in view of a whole host of criteria and moral progress. The question that remains is whether we can be criticized if we are embedded, if we are constituted by the values of a community. Ethnocentric questions can be found again. Another question is the margin of criticism we have if we start from the idea that our meanings are produced at the expense or independently of us. Is this lack of universalism, complex equality and non-denomination something that is fundamentally unsubstantiated and meaningless? One of the questions raised is whether Walzer is basically unable to justify the unjustifiable in the name of common values, even though these common values are bad for a whole host of reasons.
Despite these reservations and elements, it is clear that there are still a number of problems in this kind of approach that can be imagined as excessively conservative in view of a whole host of criteria and moral progress. The question that remains is whether we can be criticized if we are enshrined, if we are constituted by the values of a community. Ethnocentric questions can be found again. Another question is the margin of criticism we have if we start from the idea that our meanings are produced at the expense or independently of us. Is this lack of universalism, complex equality and non-denomination something that is fundamentally unsubstantiated and meaningless? One of the questions raised is whether Walzer is basically unable to justify the unjustifiable in the name of common values, even though these common values are bad for a whole host of reasons.


Walzer, since the spheres of justice, has published many books, notably in 1994 ''Thick and Thin. Moral argument at Home and Abroad'', where he shows that his approach allows him to think of a kind of basic common denominator that could be shared by any social and political community even if it differs regarding the substantial values it gives itself.<ref>Walzer, Michael. [https://books.google.fr/books?hl=en&lr=&id=r18FDgAAQBAJ&oi=fnd&pg=PT6&dq=walzer+Thick+and+Thin.+Moral+argument+at+Home+and+Abroad&ots=mVfIRoaQGE&sig=4eD98qrVxWTpVochiTnqrs1rJ48#v=onepage&q=walzer%20Thick%20and%20Thin.%20Moral%20argument%20at%20Home%20and%20Abroad&f=false Thick and thin: Moral argument at home and abroad]. University of Notre Dame Press, 1994.</ref><ref>Chowcat, I. (1995). Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad By Michael Walzer University of Notre Dame Press, U.S.A.., 1994, xi+108 pp., $16.95. Philosophy, 70(273), 472–475. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0031819100065682</ref><ref>Curtler, Hugh Mercer. "[https://search.proquest.com/openview/fd0d3a5f0ae0a6ede2b900022b9efb9a/1?pq-origsite=gscholar&cbl=1819501 Minimal Ethics Michael Walzer," Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad"(Book Review)]." Modern Age 38.2 (1996): 175.</ref><ref>Rengger, N. J. (1995). Book Review: Michael Walzer, Thick and Thin; Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994, 105 pp., £15.50 hbk.). Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 24(3), 638–640. https://doi.org/10.1177/03058298950240030533</ref> He had a lot of thought on this subject and had worked a lot on the question of universalism by taking into question the parable of the Jews. In this sense, he produced a whole analysis by showing that behind the journey of Moses there was a very particular dimension which was related to this specific history, but that this particular parable contains a universal which has been repeated in practices until now. For Walzer, if we believe in universal values, it is because there have been cultural contexts that have produced them, transposed them and convinced us that they are not so bad. Walzer does not believe in an external moral point of view which would be to know in order to become more moral. All that we have morally comes from us and our societies and their internal criticism and historical and social work. With these arguments, he tries to get out of this excessively conservative stance. According to European criteria, Walzer would be a social democrat, but philosophically one could imagine that he is quite conservative.
Walzer, since the spheres of justice, has published many books, notably in 1994 Thick and Thin. Moral argument at Home and Abroad, where he shows that his approach allows him to think of a kind of basic common denominator that could be shared by any social and political community even if it differs regarding the substantial values it gives itself. He had a lot of thought on this subject and had worked a lot on the question of universalism by taking into question the parable of the Jews. In this sense, he produced a whole analysis by showing that behind the journey of Moses there was a very particular dimension which was related to this specific history, but that this particular parable contains a universal which has been repeated in practices until now. For Walzer, if we believe in universal values, it is because there have been cultural contexts that have produced them, transposed them and convinced us that they are not so bad. Walzer does not believe in an external moral point of view which would be to know in order to become more moral. All that we have morally comes from us and our societies and their internal criticism and historical and social work. With these arguments, he tries to get out of this excessively conservative stance. According to European criteria, Walzer would be a social democrat, but philosophically one could imagine that he is quite conservative.


= The Theoretical Importance of the Debate Between Liberals and Communitarians =
= The Theoretical Importance of the Debate Between Liberals and Communitarians =
The debate between Liberals and communautarians is an important debate that has nevertheless structured options in political theory since the 1980s and 1990s. Today, this debate has faded somewhat, namely that the masters of thought in this debate started from the idea that somewhere, from a strictly philosophical and metaethical point of view, things are laid down, the quarrel is more or less settled. On the other hand, where the debate has gained a new breath even if it is not necessarily mentioned is compared to much more involved analyses of political theory. In the case of the multiculturalism theory, it is possible to see how this debate is redeployed differently with more or less genealogy to the debate between liberals and communitarians.


The debate between Liberals and communautarians is an important debate that has nevertheless structured options in political theory since the 1980s and 1990s.<ref>Walzer, M. (1990). The Communitarian Critique of Liberalism. Political Theory, 18(1), 6–23. https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591790018001002</ref><ref>Kymlicka, W. (1988). Liberalism and Communitarianism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 18(2), 181–203. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.1988.10717173</ref><ref>Caney, S. (1992). Liberalism and Communitarianism: A Misconceived Debate. Political Studies, 40(2), 273–289. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.1992.tb01384.x</ref><ref>Bell, Daniel. [https://philpapers.org/rec/BELCAI Communitarianism and its critics]. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993. Print.</ref> Today, this debate has faded somewhat, namely that the masters of thought in this debate started from the idea that somewhere, from a strictly philosophical and metaethical point of view, things are laid down, the quarrel is more or less settled. On the other hand, where the debate has gained a new breath even if it is not necessarily mentioned is compared to much more involved analyses of political theory. In the case of the multiculturalism theory, it is possible to see how this debate is redeployed differently with more or less genealogy to the debate between liberals and communitarians.
In any case, this distinction, this quarrel, makes it possible to propose a rather different viewpoint on a whole host of categories that can be found in any contemporary political theory such as rights, the common good, the political community, identity, integration, obligation, justice, citizenship or multiculturalism. All these categories are thought in different ways, whether liberal or communitarian. Never, in political theory, is there a binary distinction between A and B. Rawls, moreover, in The political liberalism published in 1993, made many concessions to the communautarians because he had said that one of the aspects of public morality he defended came from democratic intuitions. This was a way of anchoring his conception of the public purpose of political justice in something that is a contingent historical product of democracy. For some, this has already been an excessive concession that Rawls would have made to communitarian criticism. Many universalist rawlsians were outraged with a lot of internal quarrels. Some have tried to defend Rawls against himself and the communitarian aberrations. The polemic is still open, but it is more about concrete issues such as global justice or multiculturalism. Walzer also wrote a lot about the just war. It is at the level of application to specific themes that the debate makes sense today and less in relation to the great philosophical flights such as the nature of man and his ontology.
 
In any case, this distinction, this quarrel, makes it possible to propose a rather different viewpoint on a whole host of categories that can be found in any contemporary political theory such as rights, the common good, the political community, identity, integration, obligation, justice, citizenship or multiculturalism. All these categories are thought in different ways, whether liberal or communitarian. Never, in political theory, is there a binary distinction between A and B. Rawls, moreover, in ''The political liberalism'' published in 1993, made many concessions to the communautarians because he had said that one of the aspects of public morality he defended came from democratic intuitions.<ref>Hittinger, Russell. “John Rawls, ‘Political Liberalism.’” The Review of Metaphysics, vol. 47, no. 3, 1994, pp. 585–602. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/20129533.</ref><ref>Mulhall, S., Swift, A., & Rawls, J. (1994). Political Liberalism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44(177), 542. https://doi.org/10.2307/2220257</ref><ref>Brooks, Thom, and Martha C. Nussbaum. [https://cup.columbia.edu/book/rawlss-political-liberalism/9780231149716 Rawls's political liberalism]. New York: Columbia University Press, 2015. Print.</ref> This was a way of anchoring his conception of the public purpose of political justice in something that is a contingent historical product of democracy. For some, this has already been an excessive concession that Rawls would have made to communitarian criticism. Many universalist rawlsians were outraged with a lot of internal quarrels. Some have tried to defend Rawls against himself and the communitarian aberrations. The polemic is still open, but it is more about concrete issues such as global justice or multiculturalism. Walzer also wrote a lot about the just war. It is at the level of application to specific themes that the debate makes sense today and less in relation to the great philosophical flights such as the nature of man and his ontology.


= A crucial aspect of the contribution of communitarians =
= A crucial aspect of the contribution of communitarians =
Notez bien que toutes les contributions à Baripedia sont considérées comme publiées sous les termes de la Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International (CC BY-SA 4.0) (voir My wiki:Copyrights pour plus de détails). Si vous ne désirez pas que vos écrits soient modifiés et distribués à volonté, merci de ne pas les soumettre ici.
Vous nous promettez aussi que vous avez écrit ceci vous-même, ou que vous l’avez copié d’une source placée dans le domaine public ou d’une ressource libre similaire. N’utilisez aucun travail sous droits d’auteur sans autorisation expresse !

Pour créer, modifier ou publier cette page, veuillez répondre à la question ci-dessous (plus d’informations) :

Annuler Aide pour la modification (s’ouvre dans une nouvelle fenêtre)